Kornblith presents a counterfactual hypothesis that revolves around the absence of the Mexican-American War and the effects this would have on delaying or perhaps halting the outbreak of the Civil War. Kornblith postulates that this counterfactual scenario is vital to understanding the causes of the Civil War and for clarifying the “long-standing debate between fundamentalists and revisionist about Civil War causation” (104). Vital to this scenario, Kornblith posits the victory of Henry Clay over James K. Polk in the presidential election of 1844 for “had Clay won, the ‘manifest destiny’ of the United States would probably not have included Texas and the lands ceded by Mexico in the Treaty of Guadalupe Hidalgo” (80). Kornblith begins by stating that if Clay’s defeat resulted from popular enthusiasm for westward expansion, then Clay’s election might have only delayed the annexation of Texas and war with Mexico; however, if Clay’s loss was caused by other factors unrelated to expansion or slavery, “his election could have set the nation on a very different course in the mid-1840s, on that might have ended in a permanently smaller United States and no civil war–at least no civil war in the early 1860s” (81). Kornblith concurs that the role of expansion contributed to the Democratic victory in the South but he emphasizes that the Whigs lost the election in the North due to the hostile voting style of New York immigrants against the Whigs. Thus, Kornblith postulates that a Clay victory in 1844 was entirely possible as his defeat was not caused by immense popular support for war with Mexico (84). Kornblith continues, arguing that by avoiding war with Mexico, Clay would have been free to focus on economic policies like maintaining a protective tariff, promoting internal improvements, and reestablishing a national bank. In addition, these policies would split Congress along partisan lines, reinforcing the second party system, and would have “pushed slavery to the background of national politics” (89). More importantly for his hypothesis, the strengthening of the two-party political system would have prevented the emergence of the Republican Party. Furthermore, Kornblith presents the idea that “under a Clay presidency, the debate over slavery would have persisted and probably intensified, but without territorial expansion, it would not have been framed in terms of irreconcilable constitutional interpretations, each with passionate popular support” (90). Kornblith concludes “if both Democratic and Whig party candidates that year had opposed expansion, and if settlers in Texas and California had subsequently grown confident they could govern themselves in independent republics, mainstream political debate throughout the 1850s might have ignored the question of slavery in federal territories” (100).
I am persuaded by the article’s argument to a certain extent. The one thing that bothers me about Kornblith’s argument is that counterfactual reasoning rests on assumptions. However more importantly, the article’s argument in regard to the role of slavery identifies weaknesses in revisionist and fundamentalist thinking about the causation of the Civil War. Kornblith alleges that early twentieth-century revisionists argue that the Civil War could have been avoided because slavery would have gone into rapid decline over the next generation (90). However, Kornblith suggests “for all their analytical differences, recent historians of the political economy of the Old South have agreed on one crucial point: southern slavery was not nearing a peaceful conversion to free labor when the Civil War broke out” (92). Thus for Kornblith, if Clay had won, the fate of slavery rested on the “relative strength of proslavery and antislavery forces in American politics” (92). Regarding the fundamentalists, Kornblith summarizes their argument, stating that “removing other historical factors would have made little or no difference” for fundamentalists (79). However as Kornblith postulates: had Clay won the election of 1844 and thus avoided war with Mexico, his implementation of economic policies would have reinvigorated the two-party system and would have pushed slavery to the background. Furthermore, even if slavery did persist (as Kornblith alleges it would have regardless of Clay’s victory), the Wilmot Proviso and subsequent debates over the Compromise of 1850 and the Kansas-Nebraska Act would not have happened because the Nebraska Territory would have been organized on the basis of the Missouri Compromise with little congressional debate. Thus, the fact that Kornblith’s article presents a reasonable argument for at least halting the outbreak of war lends doubt to the fundamentalist viewpoint that the social and cultural systems of the North and the South were too different for reconciliation and that war could not have been avoided.